Answer:
Your answer is B
Step-by-step explanation:
Take 300 and subtract it by 99 you'll get 201
3 times 67 is 201
Which is why your answer is B!
Hope this helps! -Queenb369
(P.S, If you could give me the brainlist if i'm right, that will be great thanks!)
Answer:
C
Step-by-step explanation:
What makes a function is if each input or x-value has EXACTLY one output or y-value.
a. is wrong because the x value 1, has both an output of 1 and 4
b. is wrong because -1 is repeated 4 times with all different outputs
c. is correct because each input has exactly one output. None of the x values repeat itself
d. is wrong because -1 has 2 outputs.
so this is what makes a function and what doesn't. Hope this helps!
What are you trying to find?
Answer:
24 ^people because if one pizza is for 3 personnes its 8x3=24
Step-by-step explanation:
Answer: The square root of π has attracted attention for almost as long as π itself. When you’re an ancient Greek mathematician studying circles and squares and playing with straightedges and compasses, it’s natural to try to find a circle and a square that have the same area. If you start with the circle and try to find the square, that’s called squaring the circle. If your circle has radius r=1, then its area is πr2 = π, so a square with side-length s has the same area as your circle if s2 = π, that is, if s = sqrt(π). It’s well-known that squaring the circle is impossible in the sense that, if you use the classic Greek tools in the classic Greek manner, you can’t construct a square whose side-length is sqrt(π) (even though you can approximate it as closely as you like); see David Richeson’s new book listed in the References for lots more details about this. But what’s less well-known is that there are (at least!) two other places in mathematics where the square root of π crops up: an infinite product that on its surface makes no sense, and a calculus problem that you can use a surface to solve.
Step-by-step explanation: this is the same paragraph The square root of π has attracted attention for almost as long as π itself. When you’re an ancient Greek mathematician studying circles and squares and playing with straightedges and compasses, it’s natural to try to find a circle and a square that have the same area. If you start with the circle and try to find the square, that’s called squaring the circle. If your circle has radius r=1, then its area is πr2 = π, so a square with side-length s has the same area as your circle if s2 = π, that is, if s = sqrt(π). It’s well-known that squaring the circle is impossible in the sense that, if you use the classic Greek tools in the classic Greek manner, you can’t construct a square whose side-length is sqrt(π) (even though you can approximate it as closely as you like); see David Richeson’s new book listed in the References for lots more details about this. But what’s less well-known is that there are (at least!) two other places in mathematics where the square root of π crops up: an infinite product that on its surface makes no sense, and a calculus problem that you can use a surface to solve.